Social Justice, Libertarianism
The Conversation at Cato Unbound
My final contribution to the conversation at Cato Unbound is now up.
Here, from the Cato Unbound site, is the complete index of the discussion. Peruse at your leisure!
Lead Essay
- A Bleeding Heart History of Libertarianism by Matt Zwolinski and John Tomasi
Matt Zwolinski and John Tomasi propose to refocus the libertarian movement. Although they agree that individual property rights are important, they propose to return libertarianism to its nineteenth-century intellectual roots. They argue that the classical liberals valued property rights for different reasons, perhaps, than we in the movement value them now: Property rights were intended to protect the least well-off workers in society. A “neoclassical liberal” would not advocate a welfare state, but would certainly value social justice; his means of attaining it would be through the institutions of property and contract.
Response Essays
- In Praise of Bleeding Heart Absolutism by Roderick T. Long
Roderick T. Long criticizes the sharp distinctions drawn by Zwolinski and Tomasi between nineteenth-century classical liberals and the “Unholy Trinity” of Mises, Rand, and Rothbard. He suggests many areas in which the earlier thinkers were not as Zwolinski and Tomasi characterize them, as well as several where Mises, Rand, and Rothbard don’t conform either. Long stresses the importance of class analysis in the thought of nineteenth-century classical liberals and points to its resurrection as a key aspect of Rothbard’s thought in particular. This, he suggests, points the way toward a “bleeding-heart absolutism” – an ideology critical of every form of state power, yet also prioritizing the moral claims of the poorest in society. - Natural Rights + ? by David D. Friedman
David Friedman argues that the pre-twentieth century classical liberals were motivated not by a concern for the poor per se, but by utilitarian reasoning. The “working poor” were a large majority of society in their time, and authors like Adam Smith must be read in their historical context. Doing so reveals Smith to be a progenitor of Jeremy Bentham, not John Rawls. Utilitarianism brings problems of its own, of course, but it should not be confused with social justice. - Let’s Reject the Purity Test by Alexander McCobin
Alexander McCobin argues that libertarians often engage in unproductive debates about who or what is “more” libertarian. One thing lost in these debates is that, across the wide sweep of intellectual history, significant libertarian figures have usually felt free to draw from a wide array of justifications and policy approaches. Each was a product of a particular historical era, and there is no reason to find fault with any of them simply on that account. To advance liberty, we should think and write about libertarian principles in terms that unbiased observers will find persuasive today.
The Conversation
- Some Questions for the Panel by David D. Friedman
- Property Absolutism and Social Justice by Matt Zwolinski and John Tomasi
- Why “Social” Justice? More Questions for Zwolinski and Tomasi by David D. Friedman
- On “Concern for the Poor” by Matt Zwolinski
- Best of the Blogs The Editors’ pick of notable blog posts and commentary on this month’s issue.
- The Bleeding-Heart Absolutist Strikes Back by Roderick T. Long
- Defining Libertarianism by Alexander McCobin
- More Libertarian Than Thou by Roderick T. Long
- Clarity on How to Justify Economic Systems by David D. Friedman
- Some Final Thoughts by Matt Zwolinski
- Three Parthian Shots by Roderick Long